Dr. Frank Putnam vs. Dr. Paul McHugh on Multiple Personality as a Valid Medical Condition
(notice there's no suggestion that multiple personality just is.)
Source: Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, July 1995 v34 n7 p957(3).
Title: Resolved: multiple personality disorder is an individually and
socially created artifact.
Author: Paul R. McHugh
Abstract: Multiple personality disorder (MPD) is a form of hysteria
induced by therapists by asking patients about alter personalities.
Therapists resort to persuasion to influence patients to commit
themselves to having MPD thus forcing them to act in a manner consistent
with the role. Being so, MPD is simply a socially-created behavioral
disorder. Since MPD works on persuasion, any diagnosis to correct this
disorder should involve some form of counterpersuasion.
Subjects: Multiple personality - Evaluation
Hysteria (Social psychology) - Evaluation
Mental illness - Diagnosis
Electronic Collection: A17150173 RN: A17150173
Full Text COPYRIGHT American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 1995
Where's hysteria now that we need it? With DSM-IV, psychiatrists have
developed a common language and a common approach to diagnosis. But in the
process of operationalizing diagnoses, we may have lost some concepts about
patient behavior. The term "hysteria" disappeared when DSM-III was
published; without it, psychiatrists have been deprived of a scientific
concept essential to the development of new ideas: the null hypothesis. This
loss hits home with the epidemic of multiple personality disorder (MPD).
The work of Talcott Parsons (1964), David Mechanic (1978), and Isidore
Pilowsky (1969) taught psychiatrists to appreciate that phenomena such
as hysterical paralyses, blindness, and pseudoseizures were actually
behaviors with a goal: achieving the "sick role." Inspired by Parsons,
Mechanic and Pilowsky used the term "abnormal illness behavior" in lieu
of hysteria. Their approach eliminated the stigma of malingering that
had been implied in hysteria and indicated that patients could take on
such behavior without fraudulent intent. They were describing an old
reality of medical experience.
Some people - experiencing emotional distress in the face of a variety
of life circumstances and conflicts - complain to doctors about physical
or psychological symptoms that they claim are signs of illness.
Sometimes they display gross impairments of movement or consciousness;
sometimes the features are subtle and changing. These complaints prompt
doctors to launch investigations in laboratories, to conduct elaborate
and sometimes dangerous studies of the brain or body, and to consult
with experts, who examine the patient for esoteric disease. As the
investigation proceeds, the patient may become still more persuaded that
an illness is at work and begin to model the signs of disorder on the
subtle suggestions of the physician's inquiry. For example, a patient
with complaints of occasional lapses in alertness might - in the course
of investigations that include visits to the epilepsy clinic and to the
EEG laboratory for sleep studies, photic stimulation, and nasopharyngeal
leads - gradually develop the frenzied thrashing movements of the limbs
that require the protective attention of several nurses and hospital
aides.
Eventually, with the patient no better and the investigations proving
fruitless, a psychiatric consultant alert to the concept of hysteria and
its contemporary link to the "sick role" might recognize that the
patient's disorder is not an epileptic but a behavioral one. The patient
is displaying movements that attract medical attention and provide the
privileges of patienthood.
Talcott Parsons, the Harvard sociologist, pointed out in the 1950s that
medicine was an organized component of our society intended to aid,
through professional knowledge, the sick and the impaired. To accomplish
this, certain individuals - physicians - are licensed by society to
decide not only how to manage the sick, but to choose and distinguish
the sick from other impaired people. Such an identification can provide
these "sick" individuals with certain social privileges, i.e., rest,
freedom from employment, and support from others during the reign of the
condition. The person given the appellation "sick" by the social
spokesman - the physician - was assumed by the society to respond to
these privileges with other actions, i.e., cooperating with the
intrusions of investigators of the illness and making every effort at
rehabilitation so as to return to health. The hidden assumption is that
the burdens and pains of illness act to drive the patient toward these
cooperative actions with the physicians and thus to be happy to
relinquish the few small pleasures that can be found in being treated as
a victim of sickness.
However, because there are advantages to the sick role, there are some
situations in which a person might seek this role without a "ticket of
admission," a disease. This is hardly a remarkable idea as almost anyone
has noticed the temptation to "call in sick" when troubles are afoot.
But in some patients - those with emotional conflicts, weakened
self-criticism, and high suggestibility - this temptation can be
transformed, usually with some prompting, into the conviction that they
are infirm. This kind of patient may, in fact, use more and more
information from the medical profession's vities to amplify the
expression of the infirmity.
Psychiatrists have known about these matters of social and psychological
dynamics for more than 100 years. They were brought vividly to attention
by the distinguished pupil of Jean-Martin Charcot, Joseph Babinski (he
of the plantar response). Like Sigmund Freud and Pierre Janet, Babinski
had observed Charcot manage patients with, what Charcot called,
"hysteroepilepsy." But Babinski was convinced that hysteroepilepsy was
not a new disorder. He believed that the women at Charcot's clinic were
being persuaded - and not so subtly - to take on the features of
epilepsy by the interest Charcot and his assistants expressed (Babinski
and Froment, 1918). Babinski also believed that these women were
vulnerable to this persuasion because of distressing states of mind
provoked in their life circumstances and their roles as intriguing
patients and the subject of attention from ny distinguished physicians
who offered them a haven of care.
Babinski was bringing the null hypothesis to Charcot and with it, not a
rejection of these women as legitimate victims of some problem, but an
appreciation that behaving as if epileptic obscured reality and made
helping their actual problem difficult. Babinski wrote that just as
hysteroepilepsy rested on persuasion, so a form of counterpersuasion
could correct it. He demonstrated that thesimproved when they were taken
from the wards and clinics where other afflicted women - epileptic and
pseudoepileptic - were housed and when the attention of the staff was
turned away from their seizures and onto their lives. These measures -
isolation and countersuggestion - had the advantage of limiting the
rewards for the behavior and of prompting a search for and treatment of
the troubles in the personal life.
All this became embedded in the concept of hysteria and needs to be
reapplied in the understanding of MPD. The patients I have seen have
been referred to the Johns Hopkins Health System because elsewhere they
have become stuck in the process of therapy. The histories are similar.
They were mostly women who in the course of some distress sought
psychiatric assistance. In the course of this assistance - and often
early in the process - a therapist offered them a fairly crude
suggestion that they might harbor some "alter" personalities. As an
example of the crudity of the suggestions to the patient, I offer this
published direction of how to both make the diagnosis and elicit "alters":
The sine qua non of MPD is a second personality who at some time comes out
and takes executive control of the patient's behavior. It may happen that an
alter personality will reveal itself to you during this [assessment]
process, but more likely it will not. So you may have to elicit an alter
personality. . . . To begprocess of eliciting an alter, you can begin
by indirect questioning such as, "Have you ever felt like another part of
you does things that you can't control?" If she gives positive or ambiguous
responses, ask for specific examples. You are trying to develop a picture of
what the alter personality is like. . . . At this point, you might ask the
host personality, "Does this set of feelings have a name?" Occasionally you
will get a name. Often the host personality will not know. You can then
focus on a particular event or set of behaviors and follow up on those. For
instance, you can ask, "Can I talk to the part of you who is taking those
long drives to the country? (Buie, 1992, p. 3).
Once the patient permits the therapist to "talk to the part . . . who is
taking those long drives," the patient is committed to having MPD and is
forced to act in ways consistent with this role. The patient is then
placed into care on units or in services - often titled "the
dissociative service" - at the institution. She meets other patients
with the same compliant responses to therapists' suggestions. She and
the staff begin a continuous search for other "alters." With the
discovery of the first "alter," the barrier of self-criticism and
self-observation is breached. No obstacles to invention remain.
Countless numbers of personalities emerge over time. What began as two
or three may develop to 99 or 100. The distressing symptoms continue as
long as therapeutic attention is focused on finding more alters and
sustaining the view that the problems relate to an "intriguing capacity"
to dissociate or fractionate the self.
At Johns Hopkins, we see patients in whom MPD has been diagnosed because
symptoms of depression have continued despite therapy elsewhere. Our
referrals have been few and our experience, therefore, is only now
building, probably because our views - that MPD may be a
therapist-induced artifact - have only recently become generally known
in our community (McHugh, 1995).
We seem to challenge the widely accepted view and to "turn back the
clock." The referrals that come to us often arrive with obstacles to our
therapeutic plans. Patients and their referring therapists often wish to
stay in regular contact (two to three times weekly) and to continue
their work on MPD. At the same time, we at Hopkins are expected to treat
the depression or some other supposed "side issue." We, however,
following the isolation and countersuggestion approach, try to bring
about, at least temporarily, a separation of the patient from the staff
and the support groups that sustain the focus on "alters." We refuse to
talk to "alters" but rather encourage our patients to review their
present difficulties, thus applying the concept of "abnormal illness
behavior" to their condition.
The advocates for MPD are in the same position as Charcot was when
Babinski offered his proposal of the null hypothesis. As in any
scientific discussion, it is not the responsibility of the proposers of
the null hypothesis to prove its likelihood. That hypothesis simply
claims that nothing special has been discovered. I claim the same in
this debate. The investigators proposing a new entity must demonstrate
that the null hypothesis should be rejected.
In most of the discussions by champions of MPD just the opposite occurs.
Not only is the null hypothesis discarded without any compelling reason,
but nonrelevant information is presented to justify a uniqueness to MPD.
Perhaps most common proposal is that MPD must exist in the way proposed
because it is included in DSM-IV and operational criteria are available
to make the diagnosis. This is a misunderstanding of DSM-IV. It provides
a way in which a diagnosis can be reliably applied to a patient, but it
does not in any way validate the existence of the condition or negate a
null hypothesis about it.
Charcot had quite reliable ways of diagnosing hyster-oepilepsy. It just
did not exist as he thought it did, but rather it was a behavior seeking
the sick role. It is my opinion that MPD is another behavioral disorder
- a socially created artifact - in distressed people who are looking for
help. The diagnosis and subsequent procedures for exploring MPD give
them a coherent posture toward themselves and others as a particular
kind of patient: "sick" certainly, "victim" possibly. This posture, if
sustained, will obscure the real problems in their lives and render
psychotherapy long, costly, and pointless. If the customary treatments
of hysteria are provided, then we can expect that the multiple
personality behaviors will be abandoned and proper rehabilitative
attention can be given to the patient.
Hysteria as a concept has been neglected in DSM-III and DSM-IV, but it
offers just what it has always offered: a challenge to proposals of new
entities in psychiatry. Some diagnoses survive and others do not. MPD
has run away with itself, and its proponents must now deal with this
challenge. Charcot took such a challenge from his student. Everyone
learned in the process.
REFERENCES
Babinski J, Froment J (1918), Hysteria or Pithiatism and Reflex Nervous
Disorders in the Neurology of War. Rolleston JD, trans; Buzzard EF, ed.
London: University of London Press
Buie SE (1992), Introduction to the diagnosis of multiple personality
disorder. Grand Rounds Rev (4):1-3
McHugh PR (1995), Witches, multiple personalities, and other psychiatric
artifacts. Nature Med 1:110-114
Mechanic D (1978), Effects of psychological distress on perceptions of
physical health and use of medical and psychiatric facilities. J Hum Stress
4:26-32
Parsons T (1964), Social Structure and Personality. New York: Free Press
Pilowsky I (1969), Abnormal illness behaviour. Br J Med Psyhcol 42:347-351
Dr. McHugh is Director of Psychiatry, Johns Hopkins University, School of
Medicine, Baltimore, MD. Dr. Putnam is Chief, Unit on Dissociative
Ds, Laboratory of Developmental Psychology, National Institute of
Mental Health, Bethesda, MD.
- This is the Full Content - -- End --
--Source: Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent
Psychiatry, July 1995 v34 n7 p963(1).
Title: Negative rebuttal: Putnam. (response to article by Paul
R.McHugh, in this issue, p. 962)
Abstract: Multiple personality disorder (MPD) is not a "sick role"
enacted by patients to reduce life stress. MPD should be viewed as a
complex form of posttraumatic dissociative disorder that prevailed since
childhood. Attackers of MPD do not have scientific data to back their
claim that MPD is merely induced iatrogenic hysteria. On the other hand,
published research can show MPD diagnosis can satisfy the basic existing
forms of validity.
Subjects: Multiple personality - Evaluation
Mental illness - Diagnosis
Electronic Collection: A17150179 RN: A17150179
Full Text COPYRIGHT American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 1995
Dr. McHugh's plaintive question, "Where's hysteria now that we need it?"
speaks volumes about the failure of our reductionistic diagnostic system
to adequately conceptualize these complex patients. The short answer is
that hysteria rapidly became more of an epithet than a diagnosis and the
construct was ultimately dismembered by the DSM into the diagnoses of
borderline personality disorder; the various somatoform disorders,
particularly conversion and somatization disorders; and, of course,
multiple personality disorder. What we now know about this group of
patients is that numerous studies show that they have significantly
higher rates of childhood trauma then psychiatric patients in general or
nonclinical samples. A century ago, Briquet commented on the crucial
role of childhood trauma in his classic treatise on hysteria
(Loewenstein, 1990).
Multiple personality disorder is not a "sick role" enacted to reduce
life stress. It is a complex, childhood-onset, posttraumatic
dissociative disorder. A review of the clinical literature demonstrates
that, as a group, MPD patients do not require the diagnosis of MPD as a
"ticket of admission" to the sick role. In fact, they typically average
more than 6 years of psychiatric and medical care under other diagnoses
before the diagnosis of MPD. Their unintegrated, multiple
representations of self, manifest in the form of alter personalities,
are an extreme example of a range of disturbances of "self" found in
many victims of childhood maltreatment (Cole and Putnam, 1992).
Dr. McHugh sets up the straw man argument that MPD is iatrogenic
hysteria induced by asking about alter personalities. He then attempts
to duck the need to back his argument with actual data by speciously
labeling it the "null" hypothesis. There are no scientific data that Dr.
McHugh can cite that demonstrate that the full clinical syndrome of MPD
can be induced by asking about the existence of an alter personality. If
Dr. McHugh really believed that MPD is created de novo by asking a
certain question, then he is obligated to put forth supporting
scientific data in the same fashion demanded of all other scientific
hypotheses. Published research has repeatedly tested the MPD construct
against many forms of the null hypothesis and found that these patients
are significantly different, both quantitatively and qualitatively, on
standardized psychological measures, structure diagnostic interviews,
clinical phenomenology, studies of central autonomic nervous system
activity, and studies of memory and cognition. As I outline above, MPD
fulfills the standards of diagnostic validity applied to other
psychiatric diagnoses.
I believe that the critical question is not whether these patients have
"hysteria" or MPD, but what can we do to alleviate their distress and to
help them become more functional? Whatever one wishes to call them,
there still exist a substantial number of patients with complex
posttraumatic disorders associated with histories of childhood trauma.
These patients have a range of disturbances in self-representations,
problems with modulation of affect, elevated levels of pathological
dissociation, anxiety, somatization, and high rates of suicide. The
modern diagnostic construct of MPD is associated with a specific
treatment model. The real question is: Is this model more or less
efficacious than the treatment model proposed by critics of MPD? This is
the question that should be the focus of future debate and, more
importantly, clinical outcome research.
REFERENCES Cole PM, Putnam FW (1992), Effects of incest on self and
social functioning: a developmental psychopathology perspective. J
Consult Clin Psychology 60:174-184
Loewenstein RJ (1990), Somatoform disorders in victims of incest and
child abuse. In: Incest-Related Syndromes of Adult Psychopathology,
Kluft RP, ed. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press, pp 75-112
The debaters in this section were asked to respond to the resolution
from the respective viewpoints; the opinions they express may not
necessarily reflect their true positions nor do they reflect the opinion
of the Journal. Readers are encouraged to submit their comments about
these issues as Letters to the Editor.
- This is the Full Content - -- End --
--Source: Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent
Psychiatry, July 1995 v34 n7 p962(2).
Title: Affirmative rebuttal: McHugh.
(response to article by Frank W.Putnam, in this issue, p. 960)
Abstract: The issue about multiple personality disorder (MPD) concerns
the existence of a set of complaints stemming from socially-induced,
rather than natural, psychological conditions. In addition, any symptom
purportedly resulting from MPD is a socially constructed artifact
produced by the interaction between therapist and patient. Thus, any
attempt to treat such symptoms should include isolation from suggestive
influences, social rehabilitation and counterattention to other concerns.
Subjects: Mental illness - Diagnosis Multiple personality - Evaluation
Electronic Collection: A17150177 RN: A17150177
Full Text COPYRIGHT American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 1995
Dr. Putnam makes two claims: (1) that MPD is validated and (2) that a
treatment program that rejects that claim will be incoherent.
To his first claim, the point of contention is not whether patients
exist with a set of complaints that are internally consistent and match
the criteria for MPD published in DSM-IV. The issue is whether this
collection of complaints and behaviors represents a natural product of
mental life or a socially constructed artifact generated in the
interaction between patient and therapist. By an artifact I mean
something forged by an artisan rather than by nature. For example, an
arrowhead differs from a glacially scoured triangular stone by being the
product of the hand of a human being.
All examples of MPD that I have seen give evidence of the "hand of an
artisan" both in the way they emerged during therapy and the features
they presented. Since MPD exists in the same way that any artifact
exists, tests for content validity and criterion validity are satisfied
as they represent assessments of the elements of the artifact and say
nothing about its nature.
Dr. Putnam knows that construct validation is a task that is never
"done" but depends on the construct surviving repeated challenges to its
nature. Behavioral artifacts such as MPD succumb to the challenges that
the concepts of the sick role and hysteria provide. These are the
counterconstructs that I am proposing here, that are seldom addressed,
and that Dr. Putnam would dismiss as "simplistic." I would say that his
lists of validating methods are more smoke than substance when their
application to this issue is carefully appraised.
To his second claim, I agree that an important question - perhaps,
though, not a "more important question" - is how to help these patients.
Rational treatment depends on the nature of the condition from which
the patient suffers. A psychological artifact is not treated in the same
way as a natural psychological condition, such as depression, grief, or
demoralization. It has to be removed, not cured. In fact, the treatment
of the artifact, MPD, has two aspects: First, attention to its peculiar
features should cease. Stop talking to alters, naming alters, eliciting
alters, charting alters, wiggling fingers at patients, and keeping
patients with these behaviors together on "dissociative units." Second,
turn one's clinical attention toward the contemporary distress of the
patient and its likely origin in either life conflicts or particular
mental disorders.
Isolation from suggestive influences, counterattention to other
concerns, treatment of any underlying conditions, and social/familial
rehabilitation constitute the proper and long-established sequences of
treatment of medical and psychiatric artifacts in general and MPD in
particular. In our hands this program leads quickly to the abandonment
of MPD and progress toward overall recovery that ultimately depends on
the actual condition of the patient. This treatment program is not an
interminable process, a fact worth noting as another feature validating
MPD as a psychological artifact. If treated as though it were a natural
mental condition, an artifact will consume months to years of therapy,
sustaining behavioral invalidism. Demystify it and it disappears.
- This is the Full Content -
-- End --
--Source: Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent
Psychiatry, July 1995 v34 n7 p960(3).
Title: Negative: Frank W. Putnam, M.D. (response to article by Paul R.
McHugh, in this issue, p. 957)
Abstract: Research studies over the years provide strong evidence that
the psychiatric diagnosis of multiple personality disorder (MPD) meets
the standards of the three basic forms of validity: content validity,
construct validity and criterion-related validity. It will not be
constructive for disbelievers of MPD to deny its existence or blame
therapists and media for symptoms experienced by MPD patients.
Subjects: Multiple personality - Evaluation Mental illness - Diagnosis
Electronic Collection: A17150175 RN: A17150175
Full Text COPYRIGHT American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
1995
For more than a century, the existence of multiple personality disorder
(MPD) has provoked heated debate. That both the diagnosis and the
controversy are still with us says something about the resiliency of
both sides of the question. The similarities between the charges leveled
in the current debate and those in the historical record suggest that
things, unfortunately, have not changed very much in 100 years. It is
unlikely that this exchange will resolve the matter, but perhaps we can
move the question along to a higher level. The criticisms leveled at MPD
are not credible when examined in the light of what we know about the
etiologies of mental illness. Debate can be advanced by critiqueing the
validity of MPD in the same manner in which the validity of other
psychiatric diagnoses are assessed.
What are the criticisms of MPD? There are three basic criticisms made
against this diagnosis. The first is that MPD is an iatrogenic disorder
produced in patients by their psychiatrists. The second is that MPD is
produced by its portrayal in the popular media. The third is that the
numbers of MPD cases are increasing exponentially. The first and second
charges are often lumped together and viewed as being responsible for
the third.
The first accusation is historically the oldest and the most serious
because it alleges therapeutic misconduct of the gravest nature. The
psychiatrist's fascination with the patient's symptoms supposedly
reinforces the behavior and produces the syndrome. A variation of this
accusation charges that the condition is produced by the improper use of
hypnosis. In either instance, the fact is that there are no cases
reported in which the full clinical syndrome of MPD was induced either
by fascination or by hypnosis.
Experiments by Nicholas Spanos are sometimes cited as examples of the
creation of MPD by role-playing students (Spanos, 1986). The reader is
invited to compare the verbal responses of undergraduates responding to
a staged situation with the psychiatric symptoms of MPD patients
reported in the clinical literature. Two clinical studies examined the
effects of using hypnosis on the symptoms and behaviors of MPD patients
(Putnam et al., 1986; Ross, 1989). There were no significant differences
between MPD cases diagnosed and treated with or without hypnosis. Since
MPD appears in many patients with no history of hypnotic interventions,
misuse of hypnosis apparently is not responsible for the syndrome.
The second allegation, that MPD is induced by media portrayals, ignores
extensive research on the effects of the media on behavior. More than
30 years of research on the relation of television viewing to violence
informs us of just how difficult it is to find clear-cut effects
produced by exposure to specific media imagery. Certainly there are
media effects, but these effects are not simple and direct
identifications. Rather they are direct, cumulative, and heavily
confounded by individual and situational variables (Friedlander, 1993).
The depiction of violence in the media is vastly more common (perhaps
it is even the norm for movies and television) than the portrayal of
MPD. Yet, the critics of MPD would have us believe that the minuscule
percentage of media time devoted to MPD is directly responsible for the
increase in diagnosed cases. This would be an extraordinarily specific
and powerful effect - far, far beyond anything found by the thousands of
studies on violence conducted by media researchers.
The first and second accusations beg an important question. Why this
disorder? If these individuals are so suggestible, why don't they
develop other disorders? Why should suggestion effects be unique to
MPD? Psychiatrists inquire about and exhibit interest in other symptoms.
We do not believe that asking about hallucinations produces them in a
patient. Why should asking about the existence of "other parts" of the
self produce alter personalities? What is so magical about this
question? With respect to media portrayals of mental illness, a random
channel-walk through the soap opera and talk show circuits will convince
one that many other symptoms and disorders fill the airwaves. Eating
disorders; obsessive-compulsive disorder, bipolar illness, assorted
phobias, sexual dysfunctions, autism, chronic fatigue syndrome, etc.,
etc., are discussed in graphic detail and glamorized after their own
fashion. Why don't suggestible individuals identify with these
conditions? Truly, if there is such a high degree of suggestive
specificity to MPD, it is worthy of intensive investigation.
The third accusation, that cases of MPD are increasing "exponentially"
or "logarithmically," shows little understanding of basic mathematics.
Critics often cite inflated numbers of cases without any support for
their figures. I have plotted the numbers of published cases year by
year, and while it is true that they have increased significantly
compared to prior decades, the rise in the slope is not nearly as
dramatic as the critics' hyperbole suggests.
Over the same period, other disorders, e.g., Lyme disease,
obsessive-compulsive disorder, and chronic fatigue syndrome, have shown
equal or faster rises in the numbers of published cases. This reflects a
basic process in medicine associated with the compilation and
dissemination of syndromal profiles. When symptoms that were once viewed
as unrelated are organized into a coherent syndromal presentation and
that information is widely disseminated, physicians begin to identify
the condition more frequently. The rapid rise in the number of cases of
"battered child syndrome" following the classic paper by Kempe and his
colleagues is a very relevant example of this process in action.
A related criticism is that a few clinicians are responsible for most of
the diagnosed MPD cases. Again, a review of the MPD literature
demonstrates a healthy diversity of authorship comparable with that
found for other conditions.
The crucial question raised by this debate is: How should the validity
of a psychiatric diagnosis be judged? Considerable thought has gone into
this question. (For a more complete discussion, see The Validity of
Psychiatric Diagnosis by Robins and Barrett, 1989.) Many psychiatrists
endorse the model of diagnostic validity put forth by Robins and Guze in
1970 and subsequently amplified by others (Robins and Barrett, 1989).
This model requires that psychiatric diagnoses satisfy aspects of three
basic forms of validity: content validity, criterion-related validity,
and construct validity. Content validity is probably the most
fundamental form of validity for psychiatric diagnosis. It requires that
the diagnostician be able to give a specific and detailed clinical
description of the disorder.
Criterion-related validity requires that laboratory tests, e.g.,
chemical, physiological, radiological, or reliable psychological tests,
are consistent with the defined clinical picture. Construct validity
requires that the disorder be delimited from other disorders
(discriminant validity).
The clinical phenomenology of MPD has been delineated and repeatedly
replicated in a series of studies of more than 1,000 cases. A review of
the best of these studies demonstrates striking similarities in the
symptoms of MPD patients across different sites and investigational
methodologies (Coonset al., 1988, Putnam et al., 1986; Ross et al.,
1990). They should convince the interested reader that a specific,
unique, and reproducible clinical syndrome is being described. A small
but growing body of literature on childhood and adolescent MPD links the
adult syndrome with childhood precursors, establishing a developmental
continuity of symptoms and pathology (Dell and Eisenhower, 1990;
Hornstein and Putnam, 1992). The well-delineated, well-replicated set of
dissociative symptoms that constitute the core clinical syndrome of MPD
satisfies the requirements for content validity.
MPD and its core pathological process, dissociation, can be detected and
measured by reliable and valid structured interviews and scales (Carlson
et al., 1993; Steinberg et al., 1991). Published data on validity
compare very favorably with accepted psychological instruments and
satisfy the reliability requirement imposed by Robins and Guze for the
inclusion of psychological tests as measures of criterion validity.
These instruments have been translated into other languages and proven
to discriminate MPD in other cultures. Discriminant validity studies
have been conducted for the Dissociative Experiences Scale and the
Structured Clinical Interview for DSM-III-R-Dissociative Module, both of
which show good receiver operating characteristic curves, a standard
method for evaluating the validity of a diagnostic test (Carlson et al.,
1993; Steinberg et al., 1991). MPD is well discriminated from other
disorders by reliable and valid tests and thus has good
criterion-related and construct validates.
Multiple personality disorder has been with us from the beginnings of
psychiatry (Ellenberger, 1970). At present we conceptualize this
condition as a complex form of posttraumatic dissociative disorder,
highly associated with a history of severe trauma usually beginning at
an early age. I believe that research demonstrates that the diagnosis of
MPD meets the standards of content validity, criterion-related validity,
and construct validity considered necessary for the validity of a
psychiatric diagnosis. The simplistic argument that MPD is individually
and socially caused "hysteria" evades the much more important question
of what is the best approach to helping these patients. Denying its
existence or blaming psychiatrists and television for MPD patients'
symptoms is not constructive. It is important to move beyond debate
about the existence of the condition to more serious discussions of
therapeutic issues.
REFERENCES
Carlson EB, Putnam FW, Ross CA et al. (1993), Validity of the
Dissociative Experiences Scale in screening for multiple personality
disorder: a multicenter study. Am J Psychiatry 150:1030-1036
Coons PM, Bowman ES, Milstein V (1988), Multiple personality disorder: a
clinical investigation of 50 cases. J Nerv Ment Dis 176:519-527
Dell PF, Eisenhower JW (1990), Adolescent multiple personality disorder.
J Am Acad Child Adolesc Psychiatry 29:359-366
Ellenberger HF (1970), The Discovery of the Unconscious: The History and
Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry. New York: Basic Books
Friedlander BZ (1993), Community violence, children's development, and
mass media: in pursuit of new insights, new goals and new strategies.
In: Children and Violence, Reiss D, Richters JE, Radke-Yarrow M, Scharff
D, eds. New York: Guilford Press, pp 66-81
Hornstein NL, Putnam FW (1992), Clinical phenomenology of child and
adolescent dissociative disorders. J Am Acad Child Adolesc Psychiatry
31:1077-1085
Putnam FW, Guroff JJ, Silberman EK, Barban L, Post RM (1986), The
clinical phenomenology of multiple personality disorder: review of 100
recent cases. J Clin Psychiatry 47:285-293
Robins LE, Barrett JE, ed. (1989), The Validity of Psychiatric
Diagnosis. New York: Raven Press
Ross CA (1989), Effects of hypnosis on the features of multiple
personality disorder. Am J Clin Hypn 32:99-106
Ross CA, Miller SD, Bjornson L, Reagor P, Fraser G, Anderson G (1990),
Structured interview data on 102 cases of multiple personality disorder
from four centers. Am J Psychiatry 147:596-601
Spanos NP (1986), Hypnosis, nonvolutional responding, and multiple
personality: a social psychological perspective. Prog Exp Pers Res 14:1-62
Steinberg M., Rounsaville B, Cicchetti D (1991), Detection of
dissociative disorders in psychiatric patients by a screening instrument
and a structured diagnostic interview. Am J Psychiatry 149:1050-1054.
- This is the Full Content -
-- End --
[ Email | Guestbook | FAQ |
Home |
Multiplicity |
Religion |
Politics |
Anti-Psych |
Anti-FMSF |
Silly ]
Back from whence you came
|