Originally appeared in Harpers Magazine February 1997
By L.J. Davis
Discussed in this essay: Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders, Fourth Edition. American Psychiatric Association. 886 pages. $59.96
cloth; $45 paper.
Has there ever been a task more futile than the attempt to encompass, in the
work of a single lifetime, let alone in a single work, the whole of human
experience? For roughly five thousand years, poets, playwrights, philosophers,
and cranks have incinerated untold quantities of olive oil, beeswax, and fossil
fuel in pursuit of this maddeningly elusive goal, all have failed, sometimes
heroically. Not even Shakespeare could manage it; closer to our own times,
Dickens, a sentimental Englishman, the son of a clerk, perhaps came closest,
though he believed in spontaneous human combustion and managed to miss the
entirety of the twentieth century. Despite the best efforts of minds great,
small, and sometimes insane, the riddle of the human condition has remained
utterly impervious to solution. Until now. According to the Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition (popularly known as the
DSM-IV), human life is a form of mental illness.
Published by the American Psychiatric Association in 1994, the DSM-IV is some
886 pages long and weighs (in paperback) slightly less than three pounds; if
worn over the heart in battle, it would probably stop a .50 caliber machine-gun
bullet at 1,700 yards. Nearly a decade in the making, it is the product of work
groups, task forces, advisers, and review committees (the acknowledgment of
whom requires twenty-two pages) representing the flower of the profession and
the distillation of its thought. The DSM-IV has no beginning, no middle and no
end; like a cookbook (which the preface is at pains to say it is not), the
manual is organized by categories, not chapters. But it does have a plot
(everyone is either nuts or going there), a central and unifying thesis
(everyone is treatable), and it tells its stark tale with implacable
simplicity. Here, on a staggering scale, are gathered together all the known
mental disturbances of humankind, the illnesses of mind and spirit that cry out
for the therapeutic touch of -- are you ready for this? -- the very people who
wrote the book.
First and primarily, the DSM-IV is a book of dogma, though as theology it is
pretty pedestrian stuff, rather along the lines of the owner's manual in an
automobile glove compartment. Like all theories-of-everything, from the
Protocols of the Elders of Zion to the collected lyrics of Mr. Snoop Doggy
Dogg, the language is simultaneously precise and vague. The precision, which
arrives in cool, clinical and occasionally impenetrable language, provides the
undertaking with an aura of scientific objectivity, and the vagueness is
necessary because precision can be limiting in both a semantic and a financial
sense. Secondly, the DSM-IV is a catalogue. The merchandise consists of the
psychiatric disorders described therein, the customers are the therapists, and
this may be the only catalogue in the world that actually makes its customers
money: each disorder, no matter how trivial, is accompanied by a billing code,
enabling the therapist to fill out the relevant insurance form and receive an
agreed-upon reward. The billing code for Encopresis ("repeated passage of feces
into inappropriate places"), for instance, is 307.7. Last, the manual bears an
astounding resemblance to a militia's Web page, insofar as it constitutes an
alternative reality under siege. The enemy, of course, is hard science and her
white-coated thugs, who have long maintained that many psychiatric disorders do
not exist and that others are physical diseases with mental consequences.
Worse, things have been going hard science's way in recent years, which
threatens no small number of soft-science incomes. The DSM-IV, then, may be
read as a counterattack along the lines of a fertilizer bomb.
Perhaps some examples are in order. According to the DSM-IV, something called
frotteurism (302.89) is the irresistible desire to sexually touch and rub
against one's fellow passengers on mass transit. Something called fugue
(300.13) consists of travel in foreign lands, often under an assumed identity.
In reality, it may very well be that the frotteurist is a helpless victim in
the clutches of his obsession, but it's equally possible that he's simply a
bored creep looking for a cheap thrill. Perhaps the fuguist is in psychological
flight from a memory that cannot be borne and will utterly fail to welcome the
news that he is not the Regent of Pomerania traveling incognito in Provence,
but maybe he's just having his spot of fun. The DSM-IV is a stranger to such
ambiguities. The DSM-IV says that the frotteurist and the fuguist, despite all
conceivable arguments to the contrary, have lost their marbles, period and end
of discussion.
Not content with the merely weird, the DSM-IV also attempts to claim dominion
over the mundane. Current among the many symptoms of the deranged mind are bad
writing (315.2, and its associated symptom, poor handwriting); coffee drinking,
including coffee nerves (305.90), bad coffee nerves (292.89), inability to
sleep after drinking too much coffee (292.89), and something that probably has
something to do with coffee, though the therapist can't put his finger on it
(292.9); shyness (299.80), also known as Asperger's Disorder); sleepwalking
(307.46); jet lag (307.45); snobbery (301.7, a subset of Antisocial Personality
Disorder); and insomnia (307.42); to say nothing of tobacco smoking, which
includes both getting hooked (305.10) and going cold turkey (292.0). You were
out of your mind the last time you have a nightmare (307.47). Clumsiness is now
a mental illness (315.4). So is playing video games (Malingering, V65.2). So is
doing just about anything "vigorously." So, under certain circumstances, is
falling asleep at night.
The foregoing list is neither random nor trivial, nor does it represent the
sort of editorial oversight that occurs when, say, an otherwise reputable
zoology text contains the claim that goats breathe through their ears. We are
here confronted with a worldview where everything is a symptom and the
predominant color is a shade of therapeutic gray. This has the advantage of
making the therapist's job both remarkably simple and remarkably lucrative.
Once the universe is populated with enough coffee-guzzling, cigarette-puffing,
vigorous human beings who are crazy precisely because they smoke, drink coffee,
and move about in an active and purposeful manner, the psychoanalyst is placed
in the position of the lucky fellow taken to the mountaintop and shown powers
and dominions. Here, hard science cannot attack with its niggling discoveries
about bad brain chemicals and their effects on people who believe that gunplay
is a perfectly reasonable response to disapproval, humor, or minor traffic
accidents. Instead, the pages of the DSM-IV are replete with mental illnesses
that have been hitherto regarded as perfectly normal behavior. The therapist is
invited not merely to play God but to play lawyer - to some minds, a superior
calling -- and to indulge in a favorite diversion of the American legal
profession known as "recruiting a fee."
By confining themselves to a single interpretation of the human dilemma -- madness -- the DSM-IV's authors have joined the monkeys-and-typewriters school
of foul-weather marksmanship: give a hunter an infinite amount of ammunition,
an infinite amount of time, a distant target shrouded in fog, and the hunter
will sometimes hit the target and sometimes will hit something else:
"The essential feature of Shared Psychotic Disorder (Folie a Deux) is a
delusion that develops in an individual who is involved in a close relationship
with another person (sometimes termed the "inducer" or "the primary case") who
already has a Psychotic Disorder with prominent delusions (Criterion A). The
individual comes to share the delusional beliefs of the primary case in whole
or in part (Criterion B). The delusion is not better accounted for by another
Psychotic Disorder (e.g. Schizophrenia) or a Mood Disorder With Psychotic
Features and is not due to the direct physiological effects of a substance
(e.g. amphetamine) or a general medical condition (e.g. brain tumor) (Criterion
C)...The content of the shared delusional beliefs...can include relatively
bizarre delusions (e.g. that radiation is being transmitted into an apartment
from a hostile foreign power, causing indigestion and diarrhea), mood-congruent
delusions (e.g., that the primary case will soon receive a film contract for $2
million...), or the nonbizarre delusions that are characteristic of Delusional
Disorder (e.g., the FBI is tapping the family telephone and trailing family
members when they go out). Usually the primary case in Shared Psychotic
Disorder is dominant..."
Jargon, redundancy, and turgidity aside, what we have here is a fairly
accurate description of Newt Gingrich's House of Representatives. The billing
code is 297.3.
The same uncanny, if accidental, ability to describe the nation's movers and
shakers crops up again and again in the DSM-IV. Between them, Bill and Hillary
Clinton meet all the diagnostic criteria for Narcissistic Personality Disorder.
("1) has a grandiose sense of self-importance...; 2) is preoccupied with
fantasies of unlimited success...; 4) requires excessive admiration; 5) has a
sense of entitlement...; 6) is interpersonally exploitative...; 7) lacks
empathy: is unwilling to recognize or identify with the feelings and needs of
others; 8) is often envious of others or believes that others are envious of
him...; 9) shows arrogant, haughty behaviors or attitudes."
And it is also clear that Bipolar Disorders I (296.01, 296.41. 296.42. 296.43,
296.44, 296.45, 296.46, 296.40) and II (296.89) -- which include Manic Episode
(296.00), Mixed Episode (296.61, 296.62, 296.63. 296.64, 296.65, 296.66,
296.60), and Hypomanic Episode (296.40) -- may be combined with Antisocial
Personality Disorder (301.7) to account for an inflated sense of personal
brilliance, a willingness to play fast and loose with other people's money, an
urge to instruct the nation, and an inability to foresee the consequences of
one's actions. Closely associated maladies are, apparently, plagiarism and the
wearing of inappropriate garb. By this definition, most of Wall Street is
completely crackers.
Welcome to the broad pathological world of the ingenious, versatile Bipolars
and their catchall allies, the Antisocial Personalities. In the vernacular, the
Bipolars et al. come under the heading of gotcha! - the ever-popular rhetorical
device of the ideologue or the man in the checkered suit with a briefcase full
of shares in a phlogiston mine. For example, a telltale symptom of Antisocial
Personality Disorder is the tendency of the victim to steal things. The layman,
the hard scientist, and the policeman might take issue with the diagnosis, but
vigorous dissent (and what, pray tell, is the definition of "vigorous"? is a
sure sign that the dissenter suffers from a Bipolar disorder and is therefore
nuts. In other words, not only is anyone who pursues a goal with dedication,
verve, and discipline a prime candidate for the therapist's couch but so is the
psychiatrist who rises at a hospital staff meeting to protest the fact that her
colleagues are ripping off everybody in sight with bogus diagnoses. One begins
to understand what exceedingly handy tools these definitions be.
The Bipolars wear many hats and perform many useful functions, but, as the DSM-
IV admits in a rare moment of candor, these disorders may not even exist. The
numeral 6 at the end of the Bipolar billing codes (themselves such a source of
rich cross-diagnostic possibilities that an entire subsection is devoted to
them) indicates that the symptoms are in full remission, which means that the
patient does not have them, may never have had them, and may never develop
them. No matter -- the therapist still gets paid.
It was not ever thus. As recently as 1840, the US census recognized precisely
one form of madness, idiocy/insanity, omitting a definition because,
presumably, everyone knew what it was. (In the 1840s, however, southern
alienists anticipated the DSM-IV by discovering a malady called Drapetomania -
the inexplicable, mad longing of a slave for freedom), The 1880 census
obligingly followed the march of science by listing no fewer than seven
categories of dementia: mania, melancholia, monomania, paresis, dementia
(again), dipsomania, and epilepsy. (This would not be the last time that a bald-
facedly physical affliction crept into the psychological canon; among the
maladies described in the DSM-IV is snoring, 780.59) Even so, it cannot be said
that the profession's urge to colonize the human mind proceeded at a blinding
pace. The term "mental illness" did not enter the vocabulary for another forty
years. Many decades would pass, and much caution would be thrown to the winds,
before things began to get really of out hand.
Following World War II, the US Army and the Veterans Administration revisited
the timeless discovery that the experience of battle did unpleasant things to
the minds of its luckless participants. As a result, the number of known mental
disturbances grew to a still-reasonable twenty-six. The DSM-I appeared in 1952;
it was the first professional manual that attempted to describe, in a single
concise volume, the disorders a clinician might encounter in the course of
daily practice. The DSM-I also described the disorders as actual, discernible
reactions to something -- an event, a situation, a biological condition. But
when the DSM-II was published in 1968, the word "reaction" had vanished, never
to reappear. Unobserved by the larger world, a revolution had taken place. By
severing cause from effect, the psychiatric profession had privatized the
entire field of mental illness, removed it from the marketplace of ideas,
abandoned the rigorous proofs of the scientific method, and adopted circular
thinking as its central discipline. Henceforward, in the absence of cause and
effect, a mental illness would be anything the psychiatric profession chose to
call a mental illness. Increasingly, and with gathering speed, American
psychiatry came to resemble a man with a hammer.
A defining moment, both for the profession and for the country, arrived with
the publication in 1974 of the revised edition of the DSM-II, which abolished
homosexuality as a mental illness. This was heartening news for a great many
people, but they weren't quite off the hook. When the DSM-III was published in
1980, the world was informed that believing one's homosexuality to a mental
illness was now a mental illness (Ego-dystonic Homosexuality, 302), regardless,
apparently, of where that belief might have originated.
For years, countless numbers of other people continued to be told that they
suffered from a crippling disorder called dementia praecox, that women
experienced penis envy, and that schizophrenia was caused by bad parents. By
the time the DSM-IV rolled around, all these former truths were inoperative,
bad luck indeed to the thousands who had been convinced, in defiance of their
senses, that they were either hopelessly off their chumps, rotten human beings,
or both. The fact that so many people had been treated, punished or stigmatized
for conditions and circumstances that did not exist failed to suggest to the
public at large that modern psychotherapy had no idea what mental illness was.
Nor did the tumbrels roll when the psychiatric profession went on to discover
(and make a bundle from) two entirely new nation-threatening epidemics for
which no empirical proof exists: chronic depression (based on the readily
observable fact that a whole lot of people, including people with serious or
potentially fatal diseases, don't feel so hot about their lives) and suppressed
memory. The profession had discovered a truth as old as the Republic: no one
ever went broke by turning a mote into a beam.
It's one thing for the psychological profession to defend itself against the
onslaught of physical medicine and quite another for it to go on the attack. In
a widespread and disturbing tit for tat, the DSM-IV displays a tendency to
claim dominion over afflictions that are clearly best handled by the harder
scientists. Leaving aside such suspect entries as psychotic disorder caused by
a physical illness (293.82) and Vaginismus (306.51), a look at the section
entitled "Pain Disorder" is instructive. Pain Disorder comes in two billable
forms: Pain Disorder Associated with Psychological Factors (307.80) and Pain
Disorder with Both Psychological Factors and a General Medical Condition
(307.89). Its variant form - Pain Disorder Associated with a General Medical
Condition - seems to cede ground to the physicians, but subsequent text plainly
reveals this to be a snare and an illusion.
"Pain may lead to inactivity and social isolation, which in turn can lead to
additional psychological problems (e.g., depression) and a reduction in
physical endurance that results in fatigue and additional pain."
On the small chance that this bit of legerdemain does not suffice, the text
goes on to hint less subtly:
"The associated mental disorders may precede the Pain Disorder (and possibly
predispose the individual to it), co-occur with it, or result from it."
If your knee hurts, in other words, you have bats in your belfry.
Even when a problem has admittedly physical origins, the DSM-IV manages to
argue that it, too, is treatable by the adepts of the psychological craft. With
an audacity that would be shameless in another context, the book devotes an
entire section to the psychological maladies caused by drugs prescribed to
alleviate other, perhaps imaginary, psychological maladies. This is a little
bit like receiving a bill from a virus. Elsewhere, the manual's logic shows a
similar taste for the absurd, devoting almost a hundred pages to the discovery
that chronic intoxication (a matter of keen interest to the DSM-IV) results
from the ingestion of intoxicating substances (a matter of no visible interest
to the DSM-IV) and often results in (but is not caused by) both crime and
poverty. The poor, by the way, frequently suffer from impoverished vocabularies
(Expressive Language Disorder, 315.31).
Nowhere is this strange conflation of cause and effect on more prominent
display than in the passage entitled Reactive Attachment Disorder in Infancy or
Early Childhood (313.89). "The child," we are informed,
"shows a pattern of excessively inhibited, hypervigilant, or highly ambivalent
responses (e.g., frozen watchfulness, resistance to comfort, or a mixture of
approach and avoidance)... By definition, the condition is associated with
grossly pathological care that may take the form of persistent disregard of the
child's basic emotional needs for comfort, stimulation, and affection..."
Thirty-five thousand years of human history says that the kid is reacting
logically to an intolerable situation. The DSM-IV says that the kid, like the
drunk and the poor person, is not playing with a full deck. Neither is any
other kid, who hits the hormonal wall in the mid-teens, a condition well known
to generations of parents whose darkest suspicions are confirmed by the DSM-
IV's version of the scientific method. Under the heading of "Disorders Usually
First Diagnosed in Infancy, Childhood, or Adolescence," the DSM-IV lists
Attention-Deficit/Hyperactivity Disorder (314.00, 314.01, and 314.9), Conduct
Disorder (213.8), Oppositional Defiant Disorder (313.81), and Disruptive
Behavior Disorder Not Otherwise Specified (312.9). A close reading of the text
reveals that the illnesses in question consist of failure to listen when spoken
to, talking back, annoying other people, claiming that somebody else did it,
and (among a lot of other stuff familiar to parents) failure to clean up one's
room. According to the DSM-IV, adolescence is a mental disorder.
At this point in the proceedings it is time for the standard author's
disclaimer. First, a number, perhaps even a large number, of practicing
therapists are sensible, upstanding citizens, who never cheat on their expense
accounts and who know perfectly well that poor people aren't crazy. The problem
is finding out who these therapists are. The DSM-IV lists as contributors many
of the most stellar names in the profession, and the daunting task of weeding
out misguided, deluded, corrupt, or stupid therapists doesn't even begin to
address the legions of social workers, lawyers, nurses, administrators, and
jumped-up file clerks who use the DSM-IV as a kind of Cliffs Notes while
filling out paperwork and blackening countless reputations with descriptions of
illnesses that do not exist.
Next, and obviously, there actually is such a thing as mental illness. Any
form of normal human thought or behavior carried to a grotesque extreme and
persisting despite all appeals to reason is, by definition, a mental illness.
The DSM-IV, however, appears to be unaware of this. The manual's lengthy
discussion of schizophrenia (295.30, 295.10, 295.20, 295.90, and 295.60),
surely one of the most studied pathologies ever to afflict the mind of man,
boils down to this: a schizophrenic is a person who thinks very odd thoughts,
behaves weirdly, and suffers from bizarre delusions, which suggest that the
authors of the DSM-IV either don't know what schizophrenia is or suffer from
poor writing skills (315.2). Hard science has developed compelling evidence
that schizophrenia, like appendicitis, is not something that its victims can be
talked out of, but one begins to suspect that the entire strangely imprecise
section has been composed with the wisdom of the serpent: if the DSM-IV were to
admit that schizophrenia is in all probability a physical illness with profound
mental consequences, then the game would no longer be worth the candle.
Nowhere in the DSM-IV is a state of sanity defined or described, and a
therapist is therefore given no guidance concerning therapy's goal. In the DSM-
IV's own terms, sanity appears to be the absence of everything in its pages.
And for all their effort to sweep every known disturbance of mankind under
psychology's jurisdictional rug, the book's authors seem to have over looked a
few real moneymakers. A number of people believe, for example, that they have
been abducted by intergalactic superbeings and subjected to fiendish
experiments, but because the DSM-IV never describes this condition, there is
nothing at all wrong with such people. A person who snores or travels incognito
is ready for the booby hatch, but a person who claims to have been kidnapped by
a flying saucer is perfectly sane.
Well, almost. Perhaps he is "agitated," in which case it would be reasonable
to treat him for "agitation" (and bill his insurance company accordingly). Is
he depressed about the incident? If so, perhaps he has gone Bipolar. And the
saucer story could, of course, be read as a schizophrenic delusion. The
possibilities are various.
This, in the end, is the beauty of the DSM-IV. Hangnails seem to have avoided
the amoeba's kiss, and the common cold is momentarily safe (unless it is
accompanied by pain), but precious little else is. As psychiatry refines its
definitions with an eye toward profit, piling Pelion on Ossa like a playwright
dressing a set, the human mind becomes increasingly less comprehensible, not
more. If every aspect of human life (excepting, of course, the practice of
psychiatry) can be read as pathology, then everything human beings thought they
knew, believed, or had deduced about their world is consigned to the dustbin of
history or a line on an insurance form.
PUBLIC COMMENT WANTED on Changes to the DSM-V Support criterion C! If criterion C is included, natural and self-recognized multiples can be out in therapy without necessarily getting a DID diagnosis.
|